In our hypersensitive era, where feelings sometimes impair the ability
to read disinterestedly, one wonders how some students are able to read the
works of Nietzsche.
In the Genealogy of Morals he attempts to trace and assess basic ideas
of right and wrong, but in the process attacks the taken for
granted assumptions and orthodoxies that characterize the contemporary world:
diversity, equality, secularism, religion, science, and much else. I found
myself cringing when reading certain passages, even though I am of the
generation that, unlike today’s, did not really find things offensive. This
emotional reaction was salutary, because it forced me ask why he produced that
effect. After some reflection, my tentative conclusions are first, that he
forces me (and most readers, I suspect) to face their deepest and unquestioned
assumptions about morality and social order, and second, that he does this with
an exhilarating style of writing that is rhetorically vertiginous and
conceptually effluvial; at times, one has the sensation of spinning in a
whirlpool of ideas that are both repulsive and fascinating.
This blog post is animated by the principle that his ideas deserve to be
taken seriously despite their repugnance. This means avoiding the common
contemporary practice of finding offense when an author expresses things that
are shocking or outrageous. It is in this spirit that I will address the
following aspects of the Genealogy of Morals: his argument on the origin
of our (i.e. Western) morality and its ideological offshoots; his assertions of
its emasculating and detrimental impact on society; the style of prose through
which his arguments are made; and, lastly, his concluding argument on the
difficulty of reconciling romance/family with the vocation of the
philosopher/scholar.
Axiom of Evil
As a trained philologist and classicist with an impressive knowledge of
ancient and Eastern civilizations, Nietzsche approaches the puzzle of the
origin of morality through the identification of the etymological origins of
moral language, and via the cross-cultural comparison between contemporary
Western Europe and ancient Greek, Roman, and Hindu civilizations. His
conclusion is stark: modern Western civilization embodies the triumph of “slave
morality”, which replaced—from Nietzsche’s point of view—the far superior “master
morality”.
As the above implies, Nietzsche rejected any idea of objective and
universal morality, whether the religious kind assumed by monotheism, or the
secular versions of the Enlightenment (e.g. Kant’s categorical imperative, or
utilitarianism). In fact, he rejects any idea of the existence of some
external, objective truth upon which morality must be based. Rather, the
essential, defining, and unmistakable feature of all organic life, including
humans’, is what he calls the will to power, defined as the natural propensity
to exert force, strength, cruelty, and domination. Not all humans have this
function, however. It is the purview of what he calls the “master race”, which
he defines as the Aryan, blond beasts of prey who conquer, enslave, rape,
murder and—get ready for it—enjoy this aspect of their animal, instinctual
drives. Those on the receiving end of this ceaseless struggle for conquest
and domination, Nietzsche tells us, are the weak, oppressed, swarthy and
dark-haired beings who are fated to be slaves (presumably that includes swarthy
dark haired Southern Italians like me). It is from this binary opposition that
Nietzsche adduces the existence of two moralities—that of the master and the
slave. The question about particular epochs and civilizations, then, is which
morality reigns supreme.
Antiquity was characterized with, among other things, the master
morality, and the language of that period reflects this. In the ancient world, the
concepts “Good” and “Bad” did not designate abstract moral principles. Rather,
they referred to value judgments of one of the two groups mentioned above. Good
meant membership to the natural aristocracy of the master race, while bad meant
belonging to the weaker, “inferior” group. Under these conditions, Nietzsche
believed, man lived in a halcyon era where excellence, happiness, and strength
flourished. It was a time when man was closer to his animal and instinctive
nature, and could experience the instinctual joy of conquest, cruelty, and
subjection. The strongest elements of the aristocracy could, without moral
consideration, indifferent to danger and oblivious to the fear of death,
satisfy their lust for war, victory, and enslavement. Here, Nietzsche believed,
true greatness could flourish.
But two thousand years ago, the aristocratic and
conquering morality of the master race—which, he repeatedly affirms, is organic
and natural—was beginning to crumble. That date, not coincidently, coincides
with the emergence of Christianity in world history, which Nietzsche blames for
the overturning of the master morality and replacing it with the moral system
of the oppressed, “inferior” slaves. The culprit was the group from which Jesus
arose, namely, the Jews, who successfully and completely overturned the moral
system of the conquering Aryans by asserting the moral value of the weak and
oppressed. As Nietzsche says:
“It was the Jews who, in opposition to the aristocratic equation (good =
aristocratic = beautiful = happy = loved by the gods) ventured, with an awesome
consistency, to suggest the contrary equation, and indeed to hold fast to it
with the teeth of the most profound hatred born of weakness this contrary
equation, namely, ‘the wretched are alone the good; the poor, the weak, the lowly
are alone the good; the suffering, the needy, the sick, the loathsome are the
only ones who are pious, the only ones who are blessed, salvation is for them
alone – but you, on the other hand, you aristocrats, you men of power, you are
for all eternity evil, the horrible, the covetous, the insatiate the godless.”
Nietzsche repeatedly reminds us that this moral equation is the
metaphysical basis not only of Christianity, but of liberalism, socialism,
feminism, and any ideology that includes ideas of justice understood as human
equality.
According to Nietzsche, these ideas of equality and justice, whether religious or secular, have obtained hegemony in the modern world, and this represents nothing less than the triumph and normalization of the slave morality, or the Judeaization of life. One of the ways he represents this development is through the historical struggle between Rome and its Jewish subjects. For Nietzsche, Rome is one of the best expressions of aristocratic, or master, morality: conquering, dominating, enslaving, destroying and creating. It is no coincidence, he tells us, that we are mesmerized by the artistic achievements of the Romans. Their willingness to inflict pain and cruelty, their celebration of strength and superiority, their deification of the animal instincts, were the conditions that allowed greatness to flourish. The Jews, in contrast, were, Nietzsche says, a moralizing and priestly nation obsessed with rules and questions of justice. Unable to defeat the Romans physically, they triumphed over them morally.
According to Nietzsche, these ideas of equality and justice, whether religious or secular, have obtained hegemony in the modern world, and this represents nothing less than the triumph and normalization of the slave morality, or the Judeaization of life. One of the ways he represents this development is through the historical struggle between Rome and its Jewish subjects. For Nietzsche, Rome is one of the best expressions of aristocratic, or master, morality: conquering, dominating, enslaving, destroying and creating. It is no coincidence, he tells us, that we are mesmerized by the artistic achievements of the Romans. Their willingness to inflict pain and cruelty, their celebration of strength and superiority, their deification of the animal instincts, were the conditions that allowed greatness to flourish. The Jews, in contrast, were, Nietzsche says, a moralizing and priestly nation obsessed with rules and questions of justice. Unable to defeat the Romans physically, they triumphed over them morally.
Of course this begs the question of how such a feat was achieved. For
Nietzsche, there were two conditions that allowed the triumph of the slave
morality: commerce and its associated psychological habits, and the priestly
members of the aristocracy. Regarding the first, commerce created the
distinction between creditor and debtor, as well as the calculation that is an
essential aspect of moral conscience. This provided fertile ground for ideas of
universal morality. On the latter, all aristocracies have priestly elements who
practice and preach asceticism. In the distant past, their functions included
mediating and moralizing the relationships between creditors and debtors that
were the inevitable result of commerce. Nietzsche argues that Christian
theology fit comfortably in this context, since Christians believe that humans
were sinners who deserve punishment for the debt they owed to God. But they
could not repay, hence the need for a redeemer who loves humans so much that he
pays the debt. This redeemer, of course, is Jesus, the God incarnate. If I
understand Nietzsche’s argument correctly, it was the priestly class of the
Roman aristocracy that successfully brought these Jewish ideas to Rome, and these
efforts were successful in part because of the psychological habits
(calculation) and categories (creditor-debtor) induced by commercial activity.
This is a complex theory and it is beyond my competence to evaluate it
professionally (that is, with the philological and cross-cultural techniques
employed by experts like Nietzsche). I can say that it challenges some of the
most popular (and perhaps tendentious) explanations of the spread of
Christianity. The main puzzle is this: how could the ideas of a Jewish heretic
(i.e. Jesus) successfully spread across the Roman world and profoundly change
history (which is all the more remarkable when we consider that during
antiquity Christianity competed with hundreds of other Eastern belief systems,
most of which either went extinct or remained marginal). More common
explanations point to its early non-political character, and the successful
proselytizing efforts of the early believers, who were willing to die savagely
for their beliefs, and who persuaded many marginalized groups, such as women
and slaves, to adopt the belief system because it conferred to them a dignity
that was absent in the paganism of the ancient world. Nietzsche casts doubt on
this and presents a more cynical account of the rise of what he calls the
“slave morality” of Christianity. In the process, he forces the reader to think
deeper about the puzzle of how this religion succeeded in overturning the
preceding moral order.
Nietzsche’s German origins, his incessant assertions on the pernicious influence
of Jews, and his celebration of master Aryan races, of violence, conquest, and
hierarchy, naturally lead one to question whether his ideas were a precursor to
Nazism. It is no coincidence, one might surmise, that Hitler and Goebbels were
known to have been thoroughly immersed in the works of Nietzsche. The last’s sister,
moreover, was a known Nazi sympathizer who propounded the idea that her
brother’s philosophy was in accordance with Hitler’s National Socialism. There
are undoubtedly many parallels, especially the emphasis on the superiority of
Aryans and their duty to rule, not to mention the attacks on Jews and
glorification of war. But I think the evidence is more mixed. Elsewhere in
Nietzsche’s writings, such as Beyond Good
and Evil, he expresses admiration for the intelligence of Jews and their
capacity to have such transformative effects on the course of history. In the Genealogy of Morals, moreover, he
recognizes how remarkable it was that a Jewish heresy (i.e. Christianity) was
able to conquer and subdue the most powerful empire in history, at least in the
realm of ideas and morality. Lastly, my sense is that Nietzsche would reject
two cardinal aspects of Nazism, namely, nationalism and socialism. The reason
is that both ideologies endorse the equality of members of the nation.
Nietzsche would probably say that this is the slave morality but smuggled in
through the back door, as it were. He exalts the aristocratic element of nature
that divides organic life into predators and prey, strong and weak, or masters
and slaves, and I found no evidence that he would somehow accept this division
on the basis of that political form we call nation (which, in any event, is a
modern invention).
Shocking and Aweing the Reader
The Genealogy of Morals is not
a standard scholarly text characterized with dry and measured prose. Rather, it
reads almost like a proclamation expressed with the certainty and emotional
energy of a prophet or religious fanatic. The copious use of the exclamation
mark creates the sensation of agitation and neurotic excitement. In this
regard, a typical statement is the following. The strong and the fit need “good
air! good air! and away, from any rate, from the madhouses and hospitals of
culture! And we therefore want good company, our own company, or solitude, if
it must be so! But away, at any rate, from the noxious fumes of internal
corruption and the hidden putrefaction of disease!” He is not speaking
literally, of course. He is referring to the slave morality which, throughout
the text, he repeatedly affirms has poisoned culture. But this way of
expressing it discombobulates, startles, and provokes.
There are also turns of phrase that have similar effects. A few examples
will illustrate: “to witness suffering does one good, to inflict suffering does
one even more good”; “at the time when mankind was not yet ashamed of its
cruelty, life in the world was brighter, more cheerful, than it is nowadays,
when pessimists abound”; “to speak of intrinsic right and wrong is absolutely
nonsensical…life is essentially something which functions by injuring,
oppressing, exploiting, and destroying”; the reader has “understood my reasons
completely—and I insist that you grasp and understand them thoroughly”[emphasis his].
It seems that, at least in his writing style, humility and modesty were
not among Nietzsche’s strong points. This seems to not chime with his
discussion of the vocation of the scholar, which I will now address. In the
third and final essay of Genealogy of Morals,
Nietzsche lays out the conditions which he believes are necessary for scholars
to flourish and produce genuinely original thought. First, the scholar must
avoid marriage. It is no coincidence, he tells us, that history’s great
thinkers—Heraclitus, Plato, Descartes, Spinoza, Kant, Schopenhauer—never
married and, as far as we know, avoided romantic entanglements. The reason,
Nietzsche says, is that the emotional demands of family and romance compete,
and are difficult to reconcile, with the intellectual and emotional commitments
that truly great scholarship necessitates. Nietzsche also says that philosophers
and scholars must practice poverty and humility and avoid ostentatious things
like fame and the company of “princes” (in our own time, elites). Women, sex,
money, seeking approval and aiming for material success—all, according to Nietzsche,
must be avoided if one wants to pursue a productive scholarly life.
On this he is not completely incorrect. Romantic relationships are
indeed emotionally and intellectually demanding: they take time and effort, and
this conflicts with the commitments required to teach full time while producing
research. This might be less true for, say, the experimental scientist who
mainly executes established scientific techniques and presents the results. But
for the theorist or philosopher, whose task is to produce genuinely original
thought, the demands of romance and family can pose a challenge to the
activities necessary to make a significant scholarly contribution: intense,
sustained, isolated, and focused reading, and incessant writing, revising, and
writing again.
I also think Nietzsche is right that the truly original scholar must
avoid seeking ostentatious things, abjure the company of elites, and steer away
from fame and other forms of approval-seeking. The works of Nietzsche—which,
although repugnant, did significantly contribute to philosophical debate—would
not have been possible had he wanted to please anybody. He had to be
indifferent to what others, elites or otherwise, thought of him. He was driven,
not by the urge for material comfort or acceptance of the powerful, but by the
desire to attack the comforting shibboleths of his age. Anything else would
have been nothing less than following the herd. This part of the Genealogy
of Morals is especially relevant in our social-media narcoticized milieu
characterized with stultifying conformity and tribalism that rewards the
seeking of approval rather than the challenging of orthodoxy.
Concluding remarks
I leave it to readers to decide whether Nietzsche’s answer to the
central puzzle mentioned earlier, namely, how the Jewish heresy of Christianity
conquered the earlier pagan order, is convincing. Even if one is not convinced,
there is value is posing the question and trying to answer it, because it is
hard to deny that Judeaization of the Roman world was a truly remarkable
development. I will take a greater liberty in challenging Nietzsche’s normative
conclusions of this development. From my perspective, the replacement of the
“master morality” was an unalloyed good because, to be frank, that system seems
to have been truly awful for anybody who was not a member of the aristocratic
class. If Nietzsche were alive, he might say “No! That seems awful only because
you are immersed in the slave morality of the West! It’s all a comfortable
illusion that denies the liberty of the strong to oppress the weak!” Whereas I
might reply that there is nothing necessarily wrong with illusions, especially
if they are essential for a decent social order and a dignified life. If a
purely naturalist and organic conception of life leads to Nietzsche’s dark
conclusions, than to hell it with it. Much preferable is the comfortable
illusion of the slave morality, especially for a swarthy dark-haired person
like me.
No comments:
Post a Comment