Despite the scientific and
technological advancements of the modern world, we humans are limited by
cognitive and other psychological shortcomings that inhibit the capacity to
obtain objective truth. One that many are familiar with is confirmation bias,
which is the tendency to seek out and/or interpret information in a way that
supports pre-conceived ideas. Another is group think: humans have a deep need
to belong and to feel loved and accepted, and this often creates pressure to
conform to others in terms of dress, behaviour, and belief. Finally, there is
the basic fact that social and political reality is much too complex for our
brains to fully grasp, and hence we create “shortcuts”, or filters, that make
perception and information processing more manageable. One shortcut is
ideology, which is a tool to simplify reality in a way that diagnoses a problem
and that creates the motivation for political action. Another example is the
use of stereotype. We categorize both people and objects into generalized ideas
that help to simplify and prevent cognitive overload, and that contain often
misleading assumptions that influence interpretation. This is particularly the
case with the way we understand foreigners. When we meet someone who is not
from our own national group, most of us will almost immediately place them into
some national category that contains stereotypical assumptions (e.g., Canadians
are polite, Italians are mobsters, etc.). It also frequently happens with
gender; when meeting someone of the opposite sex we often make assumptions
about them (women are like this, men are like that). This tendency to
stereotype and simplify even when a more nuanced approach would be better is so
widespread that one might even assert that it is part of brain’s (faulty) cognitive
equipment.
So why, then, do many of us believe that we possess
objective political truth in the cosmic sense? And why, as a corollary, do we
tend to feel so confident of our beliefs and simultaneously think that
political opponents who think differently are either selfish, dumb, or morally
bankrupt? Jonothan Haidt’s Our Righteous
Minds goes some way in answering those questions. In this highly informed
and well written book, he shows the evolutionary basis of our politics.
Evolution has equipped humans with the mental tools to adapt to a range of
challenges. The formation of groups, and the difficulties and opportunities
that inhere to being a member of a group, are particularly important in this
regard. At the most basic level, groups have an adaptive challenge over
solitary individuals, and this was especially true in the harsh conditions in
which our primitive ancestors evolved. But in order for a group to enhance the
reproductive success of its members, it had to function properly. This means, inter
alia, that mechanisms for cooperation had to emerge, for they are necessary for
everything from rearing the young, to obtaining food, to coordinating war
efforts against other groups. It is this functional need for cooperation, Haidt
shows, which led to the development of our emotional brains. The basic emotions
that all experience, like fear, anger, love, desire, affection, disgust, and
joy arose in our evolutionary past because they furthered the reproductive
success of those groups that possessed them.
As humans organized themselves into larger and more
complex social aggregations, they developed more sophisticated forms of culture
and cognition which filtered our emotional universe. Humans not only developed
concepts to name the emotions they felt, but also rules that influenced how
emotions could be legitimately expressed. But in the long span of evolution,
this phase of culture and cognition is just a blink of an eye. For hundreds of
thousands of years, humans lived in contexts where the immediate and automatic
sensation of emotions was necessary for survival. The emotion of disgust, for
example, evolved to steer humans away from rotting or infectious matter, and
for it to fulfill its function it has to be felt immediately. Ditto for fear:
in the savannah, the hunter whose sensation of fear was automatic at the sight
of a predator would have certainly had an advantage over one who thought first
and felt later.
This evolutionary account of emotions provides clues
to the question of why people generally experience emotions in an automatic and
immediate fashion. Anger, fear, love, and other primal emotions are rarely the
result of interpretation or detached reflection. Rather, we feel these emotions
first and then interpret the event or
stimuli on the basis of these emotions. Both cognition and emotion are
information processing mechanisms, but the latter is much faster than the
former because we are physiologically built that way. And emotions’ precedence
in time translates to its predominance in interpretation and in influencing
human behaviour. This will not come as a surprise to anyone who has read the
findings of neuroscience, nor to those who, like me, come from cultures and
families that are unashamedly emotional through and through.
Haidt does not stop there. In Our Righteous Minds he also shows that our emotional dispositions
provide the basis for morality. Evidence shows, for example, that people who
have damaged the emotional parts of their brains are unable to make moral
decisions in a functional way, highlighting the dense nexus between these parts of the brain. Haidt proposes a list of moral senses that appeal to, or
trigger, primordial emotion: 1) care/harm, which was selected in response to
the challenge of caring for children, 2) fairness/cheating, which evolved to
improve cooperation and prevent exploitation, 3) loyalty/betrayal evolved to
help form coalitions, 4) authority/subversion was necessary to help identify
status hierarchy, and 5) sanctity/degradation provided the emotional basis of
religious rituals. These
traits exist in all groups, and although the diversity of their expression is
immense, the emotions that they appeal to are evolutionary selected adaptations
and hence universal to the human species.
The differences between small groups and larger ones
are particularly stark. Smaller groups, especially hunting and gathering
tribes, are more homogenous and hence the cultural expressions of emotions that
are foundational for things such as religious rituals and rearing the young are
more monolithic. As societies become more advanced, different moral matrices
emerge, and herein lies the emotional basis of political ideology: the Left,
according to Haidt, appeals the moral sense of care/harm and fairness/cheating,
while the Right appeals to all five.
However, despite these differences between the Left
and the Right, at the civilizational level there remain shared basic assumptions.
The West is particularly relevant in this regard: Haidt shows that the
philosophical liberal assumptions that most Westerners, consciously or not,
presume—that persons are unique, autonomous, rational, responsible individuals
who should be free to choose their own destinies provided that they do not harm
others—are historically and civilizationally, in Haidt’s colourful acronym,
WEIRD (Western, Educated, Industrial, Rich, Democratic). As most
anthropologists and those who have travelled to non-Western countries know, other
civilizations display more collectivist moral universes, which means that they
conceive of persons as moored or tethered into an organic whole that emphasizes
responsibilities rather than rights. This collectivist ontology is actually
more consistent with our evolutionary heritage, according to Haidt, because our
emotions are evolutionary adaptations selected
at the group and not the individual level.
Within the scholarly discipline of evolutionary
biology there has been a disagreement on whether our physical and mental traits
evolved in individuals or at the group level. To some the debate has largely
been settled; prominent members of the field, like Richard Dawkins and E.O. Wilson,
for example, do not accept the idea of group-level selection. As alluded to
above Jonathan Haidt disagrees and argues that our emotional brains could not
have evolved at the individual level because their very function is to enhance
the survival of the group by creating binding moral rules. Morality is intrinsically
relational and group based, and hence if our emotions are the basis of
morality, it suggests that our emotive traits are shared because they were
selected at the level of the group.
I am not an expert in the field but I find Jonathan
Haidt’s arguments to be more convincing. The need to belong, and to be loved
and accepted seems to be such a deep and primordial attribute of all human
groups. The Western conception of rational and autonomous individuals with
natural rights reflects intellectual and cultural developments that are
historically unique: medieval Church lawyers first conceived of the idea of
natural rights based on their religious worldview of the importance of individual salvation (this contrasts
with other religious worldviews which emphasized the need to create a more just
political and social order). The scientific revolution that began in the 15th
and 16th centuries, the invention of the printing press, the
Protestant Reformation, the rise of secularism, the French and American revolutions,
all contributed to the long term process whereby the religious idea of natural
rights became the secular version of human rights that most Westerners (and
many non-Westerners) take for granted as a natural part of the moral universe.
These developments, in a sense, have taken us farther and farther away from the
collectivist moral matrices that our brains are still equipped with, at least at the physiological level.
I would even hypothesize that these developments
help to explain some of the pathologies that are endemic to rich and
Westernized societies: depression, anxiety, ennui, and anomie. The founder of
sociology, Emile Durkheim, made this observation long ago. He wanted to
understand why suicide was more prevalent in the rich Protestant countries compared
to poorer Catholic societies, and he observed that the former’s more radical
individualism led to a sense of alienation and a belief that failure was purely
the responsibility of the individual person while poorer Catholics were still
tethered to collective moral and social contexts which helped them to cope with
their difficulties and shortcomings. The implication is that the distancing
from the more group- orientated moral matrix that was ushered in by the
Protestant Reformation also helped to weaken the sense of belonging and group
feeling that were part of the human species natural habitat for millennia. I
think Durkheim’s framework can explain many other phenomenon, not only suicide.
For example, why do many young, educated Westerners go and fight and die for
ISIS even though in their host societies they enjoyed all the goodies that
Western standards of living provided? One reason might be a deep dissatisfaction
with the materialist and individualist ethos that suffuse most Western societies.
Many people feel this and deal with it in healthy ways, such as joining
political and religious/spiritual groups or devotion to family and community,
while others use alcohol, drugs, sex, or anti-depressants to numb their pain.
For some, joining a religious militant group that is fighting to establish a collectivist
Islamic utopia also fulfills this function. It is no coincidence that Islamists,
in their recruitment propaganda, routinely denounce the secularism, liberalism,
and materialism of the West. They are appealing to the frustrations of many, especially
disaffected young men or those who reject to Western modes of living.
Although Jonathan Haidt is a left wing American
liberal, his book subtly challenges liberals and libertarians who favour a
political and social order organized around the metaphysical assumptions of
rational, autonomous, and responsible individuals. His data suggests that the
development of a liberal civilization is quite the achievement in light of the
fact that physiologically our brains evolved emotional mechanisms that are more
consonant with group-orientated moral matrices—an observation borne out by the
fact that pretty much all non-Western
civilizations are more collectivist, in terms of their conception of the
universe and humans’ place within it. Thus the purported universality of
Western political forms—like individual rights and democracy—are not universal
at all and are rather historically and culturally contingent. This should give
an attitude of humility when faced with others who think differently,
especially for the liberal interventionists who often triumphantly proselytize
their creed in international affairs.
Haidt’s book also councils humility about what we
can truly know about the social and political realm. Our political and
ideological frameworks are, at bottom, different emotional reactions to the
organization of society, and these emotions are the product of an evolutionary
history that is radically different from the contemporary era. Our primitive
ancestors lived in conditions that necessitated emotions that were automatic
and immediate and that influenced their interpretations of environments, not in
the sense of providing objective truth but in terms of enhancing survival.
Hunters had to feel certainty that the predator in the distance would kill them
in order for them to flee, and this is true even if their perception was wrong.
Hundreds of thousands of years later, we humans still interpret reality with
certainty because, simply, our brains are designed that way. Applied to other
social issues, this certainty translates into a self-righteous attitude that
contributes to the tribalism of political life: the sense that we are right,
the other is wrong (or dumb, or selfish, etc), and that’s that. This atavistic impulse
towards tribalism has ironically been accentuated by the rise of digital media,
suggesting that the techno-utopian vision of internet as some liberating and
cosmopolitan force is premature.
Of course, Haidt’s argument that we are driven by
emotion is not original. The ancient Roman poet Ovid said that “desire
and reason are pulling in different directions. I see the right way and approve
it, but I follow the wrong”. David Hume famously said that humans are “slaves
to their passions”, an observation which contrasted with the veneration of
reason professed by most of his contemporaries (especially in France). Haidt’s
book shows, using plenty of data collected with modern scientific methods, that
the insights of Ovid and Hume were right.
No comments:
Post a Comment