Wednesday, September 3, 2025

On the History of Human Rights

In 2021, during the height of the pandemic, a friend published an excellent novel, and in one of the closing scenes, there is a dialogue between the main character and a professor he meets in a café in Athens. During their conversation, some of the fundamental concepts in the Western political lexicon, such as democracy and human rights, are interrogated. The dialogue highlighted how these concepts are eminently debatable and theoretically contested, which was very thought provoking because I, like most Westerners, took these concepts for granted, and just assumed that they were out there and part of nature, like the weather or the cosmos. I asked my friend where he obtained the material for this scene, and he replied from the works of French philosopher Alain de Benoist, and two in particular: Au-delà des droits de l'homme, and Démocratie: le problème. Intrigued, I decided to read them during the summer of 2025 (in their original French versions) and, similar to the scene in the mentioned novel, his ideas forced me to think in new ways about these largely unquestioned concepts in the Western political vocabulary.

 

De Benoist’s main argument in the first book is that the idea of human rights, as they are understood in the West, does not have a sound theoretical foundation.  Human rights are understood as universal, independent of culture, history, or civilization, and as a birthright of all individuals. This belief is part of the general education system, enshrined in many legal documents (not the least, the UN Charter), and motivates many political parties’ and activists’ activities. In the mentioned texts we learn—or perhaps reminded is a better term—that the seeds of this idea emerged in a specific religious (Christian) and cultural (Western) context which is not universal. Other cultures and civilizations, for example, especially in the East, emphasized duty and responsibility to the collective rather than the idea of “rights” in opposition to society and/or state.  On the question of democracy, de Benoist also employs historical analysis to show that the inventors of this regime—the ancient Greeks—had a very different understanding and practice than we moderns: similar to Eastern civilizations’ understanding, it was rooted in obligations towards, and participation in, the community, not in the idea of individual rights assumed to be distinct and/or separate from group (nation, culture, ethnicity, etc) membership.

 

Both texts were published two generations ago, and yet they have contemporary relevance, given the crisis of democracy that the West is currently experiencing. This crisis has many explanations, and the books under review may provide another one, namely, that the liberal focus on individual rights, both economic and cultural, in some cases has clashed with the collective interests of the community, generating various grievances. The populist backlash, animated by the demand for the restoration of the “people’s” sovereignty, attests to the sense felt by many that their political regimes are unrepresentative of the collective as they define it.

 

History of Human Rights

 

Ancient Greece and Rome did not have a conception of universal human rights. They had the concept of citizenship, but the practices that today we would call “rights”, for example, to property, or to vote, were strictly related to membership to a community, and were predicated on the obligations towards, and contributions to, said community. A major anthropological rupture occurred with the arrival of Christianity on the historical scene, which presupposed the existence of a relationship with God that was independent of the relationship to the group. Moreover, Christians introduced the revolutionary idea that human beings—all human beings—were created in God’s image, and possessed a soul which conferred a property called “dignity,” simply by virtue of being born as a member of humanity. Here, in fact, we have the seeds of modern human rights: the idea of universality, and the mystical notion  there exists a substance called a soul which gives the individual instrinsic value independent of the collectivity.  

 

It would take many centuries before this idea would take its contemporary secular form. The French and the American revolutions, in particular, were major turning points, although the latter more directly maintained the religious associations (“all endowed by their Creator with certain unalienable rights…”). It is generally understood that the French revolution was more secular, but Alain de Benoist shows that below the surface of the anti-religious rhetoric, the supernatural foundations were maintained, perhaps because it could not have been otherwise. Contrary to widely held views, the idea of human rights finds little justification in nature alone. Nature, in fact, is radically unequal, and provides little grounds for the ontological assumptions of human rights (freedom, universal reason, dignity, individualism, justice, etc).

 

The idea of universality, whether in religious or secular form, contains within it an intolerance of contrary ideas, and this tendency to not recognize the validity of alternative views makes wars more bloody. For example, the French revolution—which, it bears repeating, was an attempt to secularize religious ideas—was followed by the great terror and the revolutionary wars across Europe which led to far more deaths than the Crusades many centuries prior. One reason is that the revolutionaries were now fighting for “liberty”, and so ipso facto opponents did not have legitimate claims to authority.

 

Further evidence of its religious origin is that the idea of human rights has for many Westerners obtained a sacred character. To question them is similar to how it was to question God in pre-modern times, despite the fact that concept is constantly evolving; some human rights today would have been unthinkable only 20 or 30 years ago. One reason for the continuously changing panoply of human rights is that their radical individualist and anti-collectivist nature provides little grounds for placing limits on claims to them. Consequently, it contains the seeds of an inflation of rights, as individual desires more and more become the basis of rights claims.  

 

As individual rights expand, unrepresentative institutions such as the courts settle disputes related to them; consequently, they arrogate to themselves more power to create laws which override public opinion or the legislatures that, in theory, express the views of the majority. The tension between the individual and the collective can become acute such that majorities in some societies have the perception—and in politics perception matters more than reality—that things have gone awry.

 

In contemporary politics, different political groups appropriate the language of human rights to further their ideology. Free-market liberals, for example, claim that individuals have rights to property, meaning to purchase, sell, invest, or trade with whomever they please, domestically or internationally. Actors on the contemporary left, meanwhile, apply this reasoning to cultural or identity domains—for example, the rights of individuals to migrate, or to affirm their sexual identity. Although both would claim to be defending the interests of groups (property owners in the first, minorities in the second), they are both, in fact, denying the right of the larger group—family, tribe, nation, religion, state, etc—to place limits in individuals’ claims.

 

Communities may have valid reasons for limiting the right, say, to property or migration, and yet in Western discourse, certainly among an element of the intelligentsia, this is rarely recognized.  Many people, especially those outside of major cosmopolitan cities, may object to the changes in their countries or communities which may accrue as a result of the trade and migration perhaps because of an attachment to culture or tradition. This is one of the grievances which fuels populism, which is in some ways a reassertion of the claim that collective interests should override individual rights. For instance, protectionism in the form of tariffs is essentially saying: individuals do not have the right to trade with foreigners.  Placing limits on migration, meanwhile, conveys the message that individuals do not have the right to freely cross borders. In both cases, limits on the individual are justified on the basis of some collective, or the wish to protect an aspect of society. From this perspective, it is sometimes amusing to observe parties on the left and right insulting each other on matters of policy, when the real dispute is on which individual rights—economic or cultural—to privilege. (It also highlights that the much aligned libertarians—a tiny minority of liberals—are the only ones who are actually coherent as they defend individual rights—economic and cultural—across the board).

 

Many contemporary commentators call populists “authoritarian” because they defend positions that violate individual rights, either economic or cultural. But this conflates liberalism and democracy, which is another tendency of contemporary Western discourse. The texts under review helpfully remind readers that the two are distinct and in many ways in tension. The etymological origin of the Greek“cracy” in democracy points to its meaning as a form of political rule, while liberalism, historically and etymologically, is an ideology about limiting government power over individuals. Thus, it is entirely logically possible to be illiberal and democratic, or conversely, anti-democratic and liberal. Indeed, it is this divide, rather than the left-right axis, which may better account for many contemporary political conflicts: populists, for example, fall squarely in the former, while many cosmopolitan elites in large cities are more likely to emphasise individual rights—to property or to migrate—whether or not the majority agrees.

 

The contested nature of the concept of democracy is also revealed when we consider that liberals and socialists have very different ideas of its meaning. Liberals adopt a rules-based definition: secure property rights, elections where many parties compete for power, and courts to adjudicate disputes. Socialists, meanwhile, look at underlying societal inequalities, arguing that democracy is more related to substantive societal outcomes.

 

The texts under review are mostly a critique of the first not the second conception; Alain de Benoist accepts the socialist critique of liberal forms of democracy but goes further by highlighting some more important conditions which are arguably sine qua non. One is group membership, which provides cohesion, a sense of shared destiny, and social trust, and it is these which ultimately provide the legitimacy of different political regimes, whether monarchical or democratic. It follows that democratic regimes without these traits can lack legitimacy, which is another way of saying consent, the opposite of which is coercion. A unified sense of group membership also allows political and social conflicts to occur peacefully, because conflicts are subsumed to higher principles to which all are committed or adhere to. For democracy to function properly, this sense of shared destiny should also motivate participation, or active citizenship, which was central to the Greek conception and which de Benoist argues provides a standard against which we can compare contemporary political systems.  On these indicators, many Western countries fall short, with some showing that around half of citizens do not vote. Polarisation is endemic and indicates very low social trust. Much public opinion data which shows how majorities in the US and Europe do not believe that they can influence political outcomes.  And citizens have many valid reasons for this perception, such as the role of wealth and lobbying in determining policy, or the general sense that leaders are not accountable for their decisions. 

 

 

What is to be done, then, to address the crisis of Western democracy? De Benoist argues that referendums are a useful mechanism, as they help to accomplish several objectives. One is to override the will of the elite or the political class. There are moments in history when a political class and elite do not reflect the wishes of the majority and certainly not the preferences of those on the lower end of the social hierarchy. Another is to give citizens of all social classes, but especially those on the lower end, the possibility to decide on the laws and direction of their country.

 

Thus it is not surprising that populists around the world often demand referendums on major questions domestic or international. In a very important sense, they are demanding a return to Greek forms of democracy, in which there is widespread participation, and where ordinary citizens—who form the majority—and not the elite make decisions on policy. The wish for a referendum, whatever the public justification, reflects the widely felt sense that the other institutions of the policy—parliaments, regulatory agencies, schools, courts, etc—are making decisions not representative of what the majority wants, or that the political class is deeply corrupt and not trustworthy. The lesson from the Greeks is that allowing more referendums would enhance democratic participation even if majorites voted for policies that violated individual rights

Paris in the Summer of 2025


In the summer of 2025 I spent 3 weeks in Paris to carry out research at the French national library. It is my 5th time in the city, and some of the previous experiences are recounted on this blogpost here and here. Re-reading my initial impressions of Paris, I am reminded of how I was dazzled by the city’s beauty and allure, similar to being in a new relationship, with all the novelty and excitement, which obscures the beloved’s shortcomings. This time, my relationship with the city is much more mature, sober, and realistic, and consequently many of Paris’s defects were evident. Moreover, last time I went to Paris my departure city was Toronto—a city with many of the same defects—while this time it was the clean and orderly Shanghai. Similar to how a new relationship with a more high-quality partner helps to shed light on the defects of the previous one, the experience of Shanghai made many of the problems in Paris very stark. A broader lesson from this latest trip to Paris is how much of lived reality is a function of comparisons, which structure, and hence create, reality because they reveal some things and not others, and help determine the gap between what is experienced and what is considered the realm of the possible.

 

My lodgings in Paris were in 10th arrondissement. Although I have spent much time in the city, and knew some areas are more degraded than others, I lack the knowledge to specify which ones exactly fall into one or the other categories. Consequently I inadvertently booked a place on Airbnb in one of the city’s shady neighbourhoods. The apartment, moreover, was very small, indeed much smaller than the profile led me to imagine, which was not a problem for the bedroom, but for the kitchen and bathroom was quite inconvenient, as simple activities like showering, making coffee, or cooking required bodily contortions to avoid bumping into walls, counters, or appliances. It is on the fifth floor of a centuries old building without an elevator, but this was not really a problem except on very hot days. Every morning, I’d walk down the spiralling stairs with wooden steps which were sunken in the middle from so many years of use; it reminded me of the stairs one might encounter in a medieval church or castle. The main exit opens to a courtyard where the trash bins are placed, and in the evenings there were always hungry rats looking for bits of food on the ground by the bins. Leaving the courtyard and going onto the street one must pass through and open an old rusty gate which would make a creaking sound from the worn hinges each and every time it opened; the impression created by this sound was that of the typical scene in a horror film, when the character opens the gate to enter the front yard of old and abandoned house.

 

Upon leaving the compound and entering the street, to the right is the famous monument Porte St. Denis (see picture), which attests to the neighbourhood’s past glory, and which contrasts with the present degradation. 



Little did I know when I rented the Airbnb that the area is full of prostitutes, who are openly selling their services. Many are middle aged French women, and I was surprised to see Chinese women doing the same; this defies the stereotype of the typical Chinese immigrant. They were new arrivals, and I knew this because I speak Chinese and overheard them speaking to each other many times. One transgender prostitute was always on the corner just outside the building, and would always smile at me seductively as I was leaving for the library. I could not help but think: what would make him/her/them think that I could be a potential client?! When walking past in the morning, I had just woken up and had breakfast, shaved and showered, dressed in ordinary clothing, and had my backpack with the items—computer, food, paper, etc—necessary for spending the entire day doing research at the library; in terms of appearance I probably looked little different from all the other ordinary people going to work or to school, rather than, say, the type who has been partying all night and wants to continue having “fun.”

 

Going to the library in the morning was quite pleasant in part because the weather was mostly beautiful during my stay. I was in Paris for 3 weeks, and my departure city, Shanghai, was swelteringly hot and humid. I arrived in Paris during a period when the average afternoon temperature was around 25 degrees, while in the mornings and evenings the temperature would fall to between 14-16 degrees. In practice, it meant I could walk and bike—two activities which bring me much pleasure—without sweating, as occurs in Shanghai during the summer, when even short walks lead to the discomfort and inconvenience of profusely prespirating in newly washed clothes.

 

During the day I would be at the French National Library, which is a veritable treasure trove of sources for research on the subject I occupied myself with this summer, namely, France’s relations with its former colonies in SubSaharan Africa. I was able to consult texts unavailable elsewhere, and the next step will be to revise several articles on the topic and then submit them for publication.

 

In the evening, I would often spend time with friends. One was a former colleague at Trent University, who now works in Cyprus, and who fortuitously happened to be in Paris to carry out research during the same period. Despite living in different countries, we have kept in touch via regular Whatsapp calls. The last time I saw him was 3 years ago, and it was great to catch up. I have other friends in the city with whom I would often spend the evenings, and this was a source of much enjoyment, not the least because our communication is entirely in French, allowing me to practice and put into use this beautiful language.

 

After dinner with friends, we’d often go for walks, another experience which allows one to see the great contrasts in the city. The tourist hotspots, such as Parc du Luxembourg or Tuilerie Gardens (in front of the Louvre museum) are very well kept by the city authorities—clean, orderly, and safe. In other parts of town, one might as well be in a different country. The neighbourhood of my Airbnb has been described; the Gare du Nord, a 20 minute walk away, meanwhile, is even more of a cesspool. Unassimilated migrants loitering all around, homeless people and alcoholics lying or passed out on the ground, litter on the sidewalks and graffiti on the walls, the stench of urine, all combine to create a deep sense of insecurity and disorder. And the Gare Du Nord’s stunningly beautiful architectural design(see picture)—with its neoclassical stone walls, Greek columns and Roman statues—only makes the present condition even more stark.

 


Of course, most, or perhaps all, major Western cities, have extremely degraded neighbourhoods, although many of my friends—who like me frequently travel around the world—agree that it has worsened especially since Covid. In any case, during this last trip to Paris I was much more aware, and bothered, by this degradation, leading to reflections on why. One reason is that the novelty of the city has worn off, as it were. As mentioned, the first time coming to Paris I was dazzled by the city’s beauty, partly because I was coming from Toronto, a mostly drab and soulless concrete and steel North American modern city (with some exceptions, for example, the Brewery District). Toronto, moreover, has many of the social problems seen in Paris, not least in the neighborhood in which I lived for 8 years, and so I had become desensitized or accustomed to seeing many loitering homeless and drug addicts, plus dirty streets and public spaces, almost every day.

 

This time, I arrived in Paris from Shanghai, a city that is mostly clean and orderly, especially the train stations. The only migrants one sees in Shanghai are Chinese from the countryside, but the government strictly controls their movements precisely to avoid many of the problems one sees in Paris. For example, inland Chinese who wish to live in Shanghai or Beijing must have a contract for work, housing, and health insurance; this ensures that only the gainfully employed and securely housed can live in the city. Consequently, there is nothing even remotely similar to the scenes mentioned above of crowds of unemployed or homeless migrants loitering in public spaces. In Shanghai, similarly, one does not see drug addicted and/or mentally ill roaming the streets, graffiti is nonexistent, litter on the ground is rare, and safety and security is the default condition of almost every area of the city.

 

The experience of living in Shanghai is a stark reminder that cities and public spaces are not inevitably degraded, and that how authorities manage a city greatly determines livability. From this perspective, the degraded condition of many parts of Paris is the result of choice, that is, of government incompetence. When government officials are committed to creating the conditions for a clean, safe, and orderly city, as is the case in Shanghai, they can make it happen. It is a matter of political will and resources, one or both of which are absent in Paris and most other major Western cities.